Posted Saturday, July 29,
2000
by David Kelley
© 1974 The Foundation
for Economic Education. Reproduced by
permission.
This article originally appeared in the April 1974
issue of The Freeman, when David Kelley was
a graduate student in philosophy at Princeton
University.
Anarchism is, on the face of it, a political
philosophy; it is, therefore, a theory about the proper
relation between the individual and the government. The
theory is very simple: it is that there is no
proper relation between the individual and the
government--because there ought to be no government. For
this reason, anarchism is held by many to be a
simple-minded theory. By many on the right, however, it
is held to be merely a simplification of their basic
principles, with all the appeal of such simplicity. For
libertarians believe that government has fewer proper
functions than it currently assumes, in this country and
others; and when the so-called free market anarchists
say that government has no proper function, it
is often thought that they are merely taking the
principle of liberty, with great rigor if little wisdom,
to a logical extreme. And this image of the anarchist as
a logical purist, as a friend of rigor though the skies
fall, is also cultivated assiduously by the anarchists
themselves. But the image, I suggest, is an illusion.
Logic, like virtue, is something of which one cannot
have an excess; but anarchism is distinguished by its
lack of that quality. Its antipathy to law apparently
extends even to the laws of thought.
The first and most basic failure of the anarchist
logic is its failure to notice a crucial distinction. An
anarchist is one who wishes to place coercion, the use
of force and the ability to use it, on the market. The
use of force to prevent the initiation of force against
its citizens is the basic function of government, and
the essence of "free market" anarchism is to hold that
this service should be on the market, like any other. In
holding this view, anarchists overlook a crucial
difference between this coercive service, and all other
economic goods and services.
The distinctive feature of coercion derives from the
position of values in the market place. Values are, in
the first instance, the subject of moral philosophy,
whose task it is to discover their nature, and to
formulate the proper standards for evaluating goods and
actions, means and ends. This task is one of discovery,
because values are objective. It is a fact that some
things are values whereas others are not; it is a fact
that some things are more valuable than others. In a
free market and a free society, however, individuals may
pursue whatever ends they choose, regardless of whether
they really are valuable; and they may apportion their
time and money to things in ways that may or may not
reflect the relative importance of these values. People
can and of course should take moral considerations into
account, but nothing compels them to do so.
Despite the protestations of statists from Plato
onward, there is no contradiction here. For in a free
society, the actions of one person do not restrict the
proper liberty of another, including his liberty to act
morally. One has no right, therefore, to restrict the
actions of someone just because they are immoral. In a
free market, the production and trade of economic goods
are determined by individual value preferences; and
whether these are moral or immoral, rational or
irrational, the exchanges of economic goods to which
they give rise do not violate anyone's rightful
freedom--that is to say, his rights. Your enjoyment of
your rights is not endangered by my misuse of mine. If
this were not the case, then to the extent that it were
not, the market would have to be regulated by some
institution outside the market: for the market is
unjustifiable if it allows the violation of individual
rights. Fortunately, the market as we know it does not
allow this, and requires no outside regulation--with the
exception of a single economic good: coercion.
Coercion Is Different
The use of coercion against criminals and foreign
aggressors is a service, one provided by the government
to its citizens. As such it may be considered an
economic good. But it differs from all other economic
goods in just the respect mentioned. When its use is
morally improper, it does violate individual rights.
Coercion, in this world, must sometimes be exercised.
Given the existence of criminals, and the constant
possibility that some men will prefer criminal to honest
means and ends, the existence of a power to prevent and
punish this by force has a certain value. Its value is
restricted, however, by the moral principle forbidding
its use against persons who have not themselves used
force against others. If this power is exercised
improperly, if it is not used in accordance with the
objective principles that define and delimit its value,
then it violates rights--the rights of innocent people,
or at least the right of the guilty to have their guilt
objectively demonstrated before suffering punishment.
This is true by the very nature of coercion, and it is
true only of coercion.
Coercion, therefore, and coercion alone, falls under
the proviso mentioned earlier: since it has the
potential for violating rights if used improperly, its
use cannot be determined by the value preferences people
happen to hold, whether right or wrong; and so cannot be
determined by market forces. Coercion has a place in
social life, but it must be kept in place; and the
market is not the institution to do this. Power to
coerce, then, must be reposed in another institution
altogether, one outside the market and the sway of
subjective value preferences. This institution must have
strict control--a monopoly, in effect--over the use of
force, since its function is to take force off the
market. Its use of coercion must be determined solely by
rules derived from the appropriate moral principles; and
it must operate in accordance with such rules without
taking into consideration any individual or collective
desires to the contrary. This institution all men call
government.
The Nature of the Market
Here, then is the first failure of the anarchist
logic: it fails to discern that feature of coercion
which distinguishes it from the economic goods offered
on the market. A second failure concerns the nature of
the market itself. It consists in the assumption that
the market would exist without the government.
Anarchists wish to see the services presently offered by
the government offered instead by private "protection
agencies" competing on the free market. We have seen why
this is not appropriate, given the nature of this
particular good. We must now question the assumption
that in the absence of governmental institutions outside
and protecting the market, a free market would even
exist for protection agencies to offer their services
in.
The free market is one in which all exchanges are
voluntary. A person can trade his time, effort, money or
goods for those of another only if the latter is
willing. The economic laws of a free market are true
only when or to the extent that this condition obtains.
Consider, for example, the law of supply and demand.
What would happen to prices if one did not have to pay
for a good at a price acceptable to the seller, but
could take the good by force, giving nothing in
exchange? There is no way of telling. The law of supply
and demand does not apply to thieves. The economic
analysis of the market assumes that the use of force
does not occur, that all exchanges are mutually
acceptable to the parties involved. It assumes, in
effect, that the cost of using force is infinite.
This assumption is legitimate, for in free market
theory there exists an institution outside the market
which protects the rights of individuals, and therefore
ensures that the principle of voluntary exchange will be
observed. This institution may work well or badly, but
its working well or badly is not a subject of economic
law; it is the concern, rather, of political and legal
theory. The government codifies and enforces the rules
of the market; it establishes a framework of rights and
liberties that men must respect in action. Economic
theory then tells us what happens as individuals act
within that framework to acquire the things they value.
Economic laws are to political laws as principles of
strategy are to the rules of a game.
A Dilemma
For anarchism, however, all this is changed.
Anarchists hold that in their scheme also, force would
not be used; coercion would not be a feasible
alternative to voluntary exchange. But they cannot
assume this in describing the market as they would have
it. They cannot assign the problem to another field, as
we do, and say that whatever is necessary to prevent the
use of force we shall bring about by consciously
designing our institutions to that end. The anarchists
would place governmental services on the market, to be
offered by entrepreneurs on the basis of their own value
preferences and their expectations about the preferences
of others. But if so, then they can only try to predict
what is likely to come about from the interplay of human
interests. If we ask how our rights are to be secured to
us in the anarchist system, the anarchist can only
answer que sera sera. At best he can try to
predict what would happen.
The anarchists, then, have their work cut out for
them. They must show how, by the mechanism of the
market, things work out in such a way that force is not
used. But of course they cannot do this without assuming
the existence of a free market, an assumption to which
they are not entitled. They cannot make their
case--substantiate their prediction that force will not
be used--without relying on economic laws; but economic
laws, as we have seen, are true only on the assumption
that all exchange is voluntary, which is the very point
at issue. It should, no doubt, be easy to prove that the
cost of using force is prohibitive, if one assumes from
the outset that the cost of using force is infinite. But
the proof would be invalid; it would be circular. A
principle of strategy, which tells one what to do
given that the rules must be followed, is
hardly the vehicle by which to prove that the rules must
be followed in the first place.
The Problem of Monopolies
Consider, for example, the problem of monopolies in
an anarchistic society. What is to prevent protection
agencies from banding together to destroy the
competition and form a monopoly over protective
services? Is it because monopolies do not occur in a
free society? But the reason monopolies do not occur is
that anyone is free to compete with large firms and, by
underselling them, cust into their market; it is because
the only determinant of success in a free market is the
ability of the entrepreneur to persuade
consumers of the value of his goods, to give them the
best choice. What would happen if force as well
as persuasion could be used against consumers and
competitors? Why would the large protection agencies
restrain themselves from driving out the competition by
force? That is, after all, what happens in the nearest
model we have to the anarchist system of protection
agencies--the criminal underworld. Clearly the
anarchists are assuming what they have to prove: that
the market would be free, that competition would exist
unhindered, that coercion is not a means by which men
would deal with each other.
Coercion is not, of course, the only means by which
men do deal with each other; in most societies, gang
warfare is an exception. The anarchist may wish to
argue, on the basis of this fact, that from a state of
nature protection agences would arise in peaceful
competition, and the anarchist vision would be
fulfilled. But this argument too is denied him. For
wherever men, finding themselves without government,
have not descended to the level of gang warfare, they
have done something else equally damaging to the
anarchist hypothesis: they have formed new governments.
Or, in the anarchist terminology, they have formed
monopolistic "protection agencies." But this is
precisely what the anarchist says would not happen in an
anarchistic situation. Anarchism lives on its opposition
to government, but every government that exists is a
refutation of anarchism; for it belies the anarchists'
prediction that if only we can send government away it
will not come back.
Again, anarchists complain that governments are
immoral because they initiate, or would initiate, the
use of force against anyone forming a rival "protection
agency." Now it is false that this would be immoral: a
government is justified in preventing any private power
designed to exercise coercion, because such a power is a
threat to the rights of its citizens, even if the power
is never actualized. But the fact that governments
would use force in this way is another
refutation of anarchism; for such a use of force by one
"protection agency" against another to keep its monopoly
is precisely what the anarchist predicts would not
occur.
That such things happen, or would happen, is
embarrassing to the anarchist because he allows no means
for preventing them from happening. The anarchist is
caught in a dilemma. Like his namesake of the nihilistic
left, he rejects the social institution through which
men attempt, by positive action, to insure themselves of
certain conditions necessary for social existence; yet
unlike the nihilist he believes that there are such
conditions, and that a form of society in which they do
not obtain is unacceptable. Caught in this dilemma, he
can only try to argue that these conditions will come
about by natural law, so that we need do nothing
ourselves. But this argument, we have seen, is riddled
with logical errors. It ignores the difference between
coercion and economic goods on the market, a difference
that undercuts the argument from the outset. It relies,
for its argument that coercion would not in fact occur,
on principles that assume coercion cannot occur, which
makes the argument circular. And since it rests on a
prediction about what men would do, it is
vulnerable to the historical facts about what men
have done. In the end, the anarchist cannot
escape his dilemma; his dilemma is a contradiction. He
is advocating a certain end, a society free of violence
among men, while rejecting the only means of achieving
that end. Thus anarchism is hardly even a political
philosophy. It is, much rather, an attempt to escape the
responsibility of providing one. It would, as its
critics contend, be a disaster in practice; but that is
because it is fantastic and incoherent in
theory.
|