The very word "democracy" in our time has become a term
of commendation. Every system of government wants to call itself a
democracy, even if it is actually a dictatorship. "Democracy" has become
such a term of approval that to call something democracy is implicitly
to commend it. Even communist nations whose governments are tyrannical
to the core pride themselves on being "people's democracies." In
non-communist nations such as the United States this tendency is equally
evident: we hear of wars to defend democracy, and the need to "preserve
the tradition of liberal democracy."
Whether one is talking about the right to vote or the
"need to share our resources," people will use the word "democracy" to
praise whatever political system or ideal they favor. The harshest
criticism of any procedure is that it is "anti-democratic." And yet it
was not always so: even a hundred years ago in this country, to call a
nation a democracy could be construed simply as a description, not an
evaluation sometimes even as a criticism. Almost nowhere is this any
longer true.
Majority Rule
Democracy is rule by the majority. In a direct
democracy, such as that of ancient Athens, or like the New England town
meetings, every citizen can vote on every measure. In an indirect, or
representative, democracy, each citizen can vote to elect
representatives (Congress, Parliament) who then do the voting, and it is
the majority of the representatives rather than the majority of the
citizens themselves who determine the outcome.
Let us consider representative democracy, the only kind
that is feasible in large nations. Several conditions have first to be
spelled out before our description is complete.
First, in a democracy there are elections. But how
often? Suppose there were an election only once in a hundred years. In
such a "democracy" voters could not vote to change governments more than
once in a lifetime. Clearly, elections must be fairly frequent, enough
to give voters a chance to vote for new candidates.
Second, the vote must be rather widely distributed. If
only one per cent of the population could vote, or only persons whose
initials were R.Z., no election would represent the will of the majority
of the people, no matter how often they were held. There are almost
always certain restrictions on voting - e.g., minors cannot vote,
convicted felons cannot vote while in prison, persons in mental
institutions cannot vote and non-citizens cannot vote-but in the
twentieth century at least there are many times more residents who can
vote than cannot. Only after World War I could women vote in the United
States, and for many decades no blacks could vote, as they still cannot
in South Africa.
Third, even if everyone could vote, and at frequent
intervals, it would be to no purpose if there were no diversity of
positions available to vote for (or against). In the Soviet Union people
can vote, at least for some offices, but only for one communist
candidate or another-non-communists are not permitted to be on the
ballot. In other Eastern bloc nations, numerous political parties are
permitted, but no one is permitted to be a candidate who is not
officially approved by the government in power. Such a restriction on
candidacy can have the same effect as permitting only communists to be
candidates. In both cases, a wide diversity of preferences is ignored.
If a democracy is to function at all, it must be possible for persons of
whatever opinion to sponsor candidates for office and there must be
means for getting them on the ballot.
Nor is even this sufficient. No choice by voters is
meaningful unless that choice has at least the opportunity to be an
informed choice; and this is not possible if all the channels of
publicity are reserved for the officially sponsored parties. Electors
must be able to find out all they need to know about the alternative
candidates. If the government owns all the television and radio
stations, and owns or controls the content of newspapers and magazines,
the voter will not be able to receive an accurate impression of the
choices available.
Even if the press is not owned by the government, if
newspapers are censored or prohibited from expressing opinions contrary
to those of the party in power, voting citizens will not be able to make
choices on the basis of reliable information. If newspapers and the
media are monopolized by one group or party, it is not possible for the
groups which are denied access to the media to receive a fair hearing.
And thus a controlled press is incompatible with democracy, and a free
press essential to it.
There may well be other conditions, but these at least
are indispensable if any system of government is to be called a
functioning democracy. 1
Self-Government
Democracy is often spoken of as "self-government." But
if we treat this term with any care at all, it is clear that democracy
is no such thing. I can govern myself, determine to a large extent the
course of my life, curb my desire for immediate satisfactions in order
to achieve long-range goals, and so on. And you can do the same with
yourself. If ten people do this, each is governing himself or herself.
But when people speak of democracy as self-government, they are not
speaking about each person governing himself, they are speaking of a
process in which a majority of voters, or a majority of members of a
legislature, make decisions which have the force of law for everyone,
including those who are opposed to what is enacted. It is true that each
adult individual in a democracy can participate in determining who shall
sit in the seats of political power-but only in a very small way, seldom
enough to change the outcome of an election.
In any case, self-government means governing oneself;
it is a mistake to extend this from an individual to a collection of
individuals and say that via democracy the collection is "governing
itself." Democracy is simply government by the majority of a collective
(or the majority of the representatives the voters have voted for).
Their decisions may not accord with the needs or wishes of you as an
individual at all. To the extent that they exert coercive power over
your life, you are being governed by others.
An individual, of course, may govern himself badly: he
may make constant mistakes, may ruin his own life, may waste his years
on useless projects or alcohol; but at least he is doing it to himself.
A democratic government may also govern others badly. When inhabitants
of a nation freed from colonial rule say, "At least we're governing
ourselves," what they are saying is that instead of people from outside
the nation ruling them, there are now people from inside the nation
ruling them-and sometimes doing so far worse than their colonial masters
did.
Objections to Democracy
The most usual, and most easily understood, objection
to democracy as a form of government is that it enables the majority to
ride roughshod over the rights of a minority to persecute them, to
censor their activities, even to kill them. A majority might vote to
kill certain minority racial elements, or to make life difficult for
them in many ways. If feelings run high and a majority knows it can get
by with it, there is every temptation to vote into law whatever
prejudices a majority may have. Is it inconceivable that a majority of
Germans, had they voted on it, would have voted to do something (not
necessarily death) to Jews? Certainly a majority of Americans for
generations used the political means to keep blacks "in their place."
When there is no criterion but majority rule, anything can become law,
depending on what the whims of the majority are; it is like a ship
without a rudder.
But a second, and even more tell-ing, criticism of
democracy is that the majority of voters will often vote for policies
which turn out to be ruinous to themselves, though they do not see this
at the time. Legislatures, responding to the voters who elected them,
may vote billions of dollars for various schemes of welfare. Even though
only a small part of the money ultimately reaches the poor for whom it
was intended, the legislators continue to vote for more of these
measures. If they don't, they are branded as "cold" and "unhumanitarian"
(as if it were somehow humanitarian for A to take B's money and give it
to C) and they won't get re-elected. But the voters rebel at the
resulting high taxes, so the government resorts to increasing quantities
of printing-press money, and the result of course is inflation. The
consumer's dollars will no longer buy what they did before, and almost
everyone is worse off than before. But they didn't see the causal
connection between the measures they voted for and their resultant
poverty. They didn't realize that if 40 per cent of their income went to
finance the government, that was 40 per cent they couldn't use
themselves, and yet that 40 per cent wasn't enough to finance the
government projects which they themselves favored.
When they said "It's government money," they didn't
realize that it was their money that was being taken from them to
finance the projects they wanted. They didn't realize that money isn't
like manna from heaven - that the government has no way of financing
anything except by taking it from the people themselves. They didn't see
that for every person who gets something for nothing there must be at
least one other person who gets nothing for something. Even a
superficial knowledge of elementary economics should have told them this
much; but they didn't have even that elementary knowledge, so they voted
themselves into disaster. Thus, beginning in relative independence of
government, they voted themselves into utter dependence on government, a
result they had completely failed to foresee.
One may say, "Well, then they deserve it. They brought
it on themselves." Perhaps so-but who is the "they"? The "they" is the
majority. The minority, who warned against these consequences, and were
only ridiculed for their efforts, certainly did not deserve such a fate;
they knew well enough what would happen. But in a democracy they must
suffer consequences along with the ignorant majority that favored the
disastrous policies.
When Benito Juarez, the first president of Mexico,
said, "Since people do not vote themselves into slavery, freedom flows
from democracy as water flows from the hills," his words were doubtless
eloquent and inspiring. But unfortunately they were not true; people do
vote themselves into slavery.
Plato on Democracy
What, after all, is so great about a majority view?
Does a majority's taste in art determine which art is best? Does a
majority vote on Newton vs. Einstein determine which of their theories
was right? Are the masses of mankind so imbued with political wisdom
that the majority can always be trusted to make the right choices? On
the contrary: the majority of people appear to be influenced more by a
candidate's images than by his argument, and to become bored and
uncomprehending when even moderately difficult points are discussed
(such as the need for capital investment to bring about prosperity).
Ignorance and confusion multiplied 100 million times are still ignorance
and confusion. That is why Louis Napoleon characterized democracy
cynically as "government of the cattle, for the cattle, by the cattle."
And that is why Plato more than two thousand years ago spoke of
democracy in the following manner:
Imagine this state of affairs on board a ship or a
number of ships. The master is bigger and burlier than any of the crew,
but a little deaf and shortsighted and no less deficient in seamanship.
The sailors are quarrelling over the control of the helm; each thinks he
ought to be steering the vessel, though he has never learnt navigation
and cannot point to any teacher under whom he has served his
apprenticeship; what is more, they assert that navigation is a thing
that cannot be taught at all, and are ready to tear in pieces anyone who
says it can.
Meanwhile they besiege the master himself, begging him
urgently to trust them with the helm; and sometimes, when others have
been more successful in gaining his ear, they kill them or throw them
overboard, and, after somehow stupefying the worthy master with strong
drink or an opiate, take control of the ship, make free with its stores,
and turn the voyage, as might be expected of such a crew, into a drunken
carousal.
Besides all this, they cry up as a skilled navigator
and master of seamanship anyone clever enough to lend a hand in
persuading or forcing the master to set them in command. Every other
kind of man they condemn as useless. They do not understand that the
genuine navigator can only make himself fit to command a ship by
studying the seasons of the year, sky, stars, and winds, and all that
belongs to his craft; and they have no idea that along with the science
of navigation, it is possible for them to gain, by instruction or
practice, the skill to keep control of the helm whether some of them
like it or not.
If a ship were managed in that way, would not those on
board be likely to call the expert in navigation a mere stargazer, who
spent his time in idle talk and was useless to them? ... But our present
rulers may fairly be compared to the sailors in our parable, and the
useless visionaries, as the politicians call them, to the real masters
of navigation.... Democracy will promote to honor anyone who merely
calls himself the people's friend. 2
A Republic
The government of the United States is not a democracy,
and the Founding Fathers never thought of it as such. It is, rather, a
republic.
A republic may be democratic in many of its procedures,
but there are certain things it cannot do. In the constitution of a
republic are contained certain limitations on what the majority may do.
Thus, the First Amendment declares that Congress shall pass no law
abridging freedom of speech or of the press. Even if a law banning
freedom of speech were passed by Congress, it would be unconstitutional
and presumably would be struck down by the courts.
In the same way, the Constitution provides for "due
process of law," protects citizens against search and seizure of
property, entitles them to protect themselves against aggressors, and so
on-and having these protections embedded in the Constitution gives all
of us protection against measures that an ignorant or whimsical majority
might enact. In short, the Constitution recognizes and protects
individual rights against their violation by other individuals, and by
the government itself-whereas unlimited democracy may flout them with
abandon, and with nothing between them and us to protect us against the
ever-changing whims of the majority.
As James Madison wrote in The Federalist Papers, "A
pure democracy can admit no cure for the mischiefs of faction. A common
passion or interest will be felt by a majority, and there is nothing to
check the inducements to sacrifice the weaker party. Hence it is, that
democracies have ever been found incompatible with personal security or
the rights of property; and have, in general, been as short in their
lives as they have been violent in their deaths."
What Kind of Republic?
What whims we are protected against depends, of course,
on what kind of republic it is. It depends on what kinds of protection
are written into the constitution; it also depends on whether the
constitution is actually followed in practice or is simply there for
self-advertisement or window-dressing, like the constitution of the
Soviet Union.
The best constitution is one which provides maximum
freedom under a rule of law. Maximum freedom means freedom to live by
one's own choices and not to live by the choices forced on one by
others. But some choices that people make interfere with the freedom of
others; some people choose to murder, to plunder, to steal the fruits of
others' labor.
Such errant behavior is the reason why law is required.
The first maxim of the law is: Do not harm others-whether those
inflicting the harm are other individuals or the government itself. Law
is required so that people may live in freedom, not having that freedom
forcibly interfered with by the choices of others.
All this was certainly the intent of the Founding
Fathers of the American republic. Such freedoms include, certainly, the
political freedoms, such as the freedom of speech and press, freedom of
peaceable assembly, and freedom from harm to one's person or property;
they also include economic freedom, such as the freedom to start a new
enterprise, freedom to sustain it by one's efforts (not to have it
confiscated), and freedom to employ others or be employed by others on
terms voluntarily agreed to by both; in short, the freedom of the
market.
The Founding Fathers saw no reason to assume that a
majority of citizens should have the final and deciding word on what
bills should be enacted into law; decisions of such depth and complexity
could not be left to the ever-changing whims of a majority. "No one
imagines that a majority of passengers should control a plane. No one
assumes that, by majority vote, the patients, nurses, elevator boys and
cooks and ambulance drivers and interns and telephone operators and
students and scrubwomen in a hospital should control the hospital. Would
you ever ride on a train if all the passengers stepped into booths and
elected the train crews by majority vote, as intelligently as you elect
the men whose names appear in lists before you in a voting booth? Then
why is it taken for granted that every person is endowed on his 21st
birthday with a God-given right and ability to elect the men who decide
questions of political philosophy and international diplomacy?
"This fantastic belief is no part of the American
Revolution. Thomas Paine, Madison, Monroe, Jefferson, Washington,
Franklin, did not entertain it for a moment. When this belief first
affected American government, it broke John Quincy Adams' heart; to him
it meant the end of freedom on earth." 3
And yet, things haven't quite turned out that way. As
one observes the United States today, it often seems as if very little
of the original republic remains, and that it has been gradually,
sometimes imperceptibly, but nevertheless surely been transformed into
the democracy that the Founding Fathers feared. How has this happened?
Election to Federal Offices
One important straw in the wind is the gradual
transformation of the manner in which individuals are elected or
appointed to high office in the federal government. Most people seem to
assume that congressmen and presidents always came into office as the
result of democratic elections. But the founders of our republic
carefully framed it otherwise. Consider how it was when the republic was
founded, and for many years thereafter, based on the original
(unamended) Constitution:
1. The only exercise of majority rule in the federal
government was the House of Representatives. The majority of voters were
empowered to elect-and to recall in two years-the members of the House,
the only body having the authority to spend the money collected from the
people in taxes. (Voting was also much more restricted during those
years.)
2. The Senate was not elected by the citizens. Its
members-two from each state-were appointed by the legislatures of their
respective states, according to rules determined by the states and not
the federal government. The popular election of senators did not come
about until the 17th Amendment, in 1913.
3. The president was not elected by popular vote at
all. Article 2 of the Constitution reads, in part: "Each state shall
appoint, in such manner as the legislature thereof may direct, a number
of electors, equal to the whole number of senators and representatives
to which the state may be entitled in the Congress ... The electors
shall meet in their respective states, and vote by ballot for two
persons ... They shall make a list of all the persons voted for, and of
the number of votes for each, which list they shall sign and certify,
and transmit sealed to the seat of the government of the United States,
directed to the president of the Senate. The president of the Senate
shall, in the presence of the Senate and House of Representatives, open
all the certificates, and the votes shall then be counted. The person
having the greatest number of votes shall be the president, if such
number be a majority of the whole number of electors appointed . . ." It
was done this way so that the president would not be subject to the
whims of any section of the nation, but would represent the entire
republic.
Today, of course, the president is elected by popular
vote, and the Electoral College is an empty charade. This is yet another
step toward emasculating the republic and instituting democracy. "And
many a president in a time of crisis, since that right [freedom from
popular election, hence from special interest groups) was taken away
from his high office, must have silently cursed the amendment that
plunges him to the neck in a mob of shortsighted, local-minded,
clamoring men, clutching and pulling at him with a thousand hands. Today
that Amendment does not let the captain of this ship of State make one
clear decision unhampered by the ignorance and prejudices and fears of
all the passengers on all the decks and all the men playing poker in the
ship's bar. An ocean liner could not be navigated for a day under such
conditions." 4
The Courts and the Republic
But that is only the tip of the iceberg. What has
occurred in this nation, and only partly because of changes in the
method of electing presidents and Congressmen, is an enormous expansion
of governmental powers. When this republic was founded, the main purpose
of the federal government was defense against aggression: police to
defend citizens against internal aggression, and armed forces to defend
them against external aggression. But since government, to discharge
these functions, requires a monopoly on the use of physical force-or at
least a monopoly on the power to say who will be entitled to wield that
force-it is tempting for a government, once installed, to use that
coercive force in ways that were no part of the original plan. "Give
them an inch and they'll take a mile" was never more applicable than to
the powers usurped by governments: power to regulate industry and
agriculture, power to control and inflate the currency, power to seize
the earnings of those who work and give them to those who do not-and so
on endlessly.
"But the United States is a republic; and the
republic's powers are limited by its constitution. The Constitution does
not mention any of these powers as being among those delegated to the
federal government. The federal government is not constitutionally
empowered to do any of these things."
This is quite true. But the Constitution is interpreted
by the courts, and the courts-particularly during and since Roosevelt's
"New Deal" have conspicuously failed to prevent the expansion of Federal
powers. The result has been to sanction Federal interference in
virtually every branch of economic activity, in which, as a republic, it
has no place.
Interstate Commerce
For example, the Constitution empowers the federal
government to handle "interstate commerce." But the interstate commerce
clause has been construed by the courts so as to permit all manner of
activities never envisaged by the framers of the Constitution, such as
"taxing North Dakota farmers to build flood control dams on a dry creek
rising in the mountains of Los Angeles County, flowing through Los
Angeles County, and discharging into the Pacific Ocean in Los Angeles
County." 5 Interstate commerce has been construed to include
the wages of men who wash the windows of buildings in which interstate
trade is conducted. It has been construed to permit all manner of
regulation of agriculture, such as regulating the kind and amounts of
crops a farmer may grow. (The federal government has the authority to
regulate that which it subsidizes, said the Court; but what gave it the
authority to subsidize in the first place?) It has been construed so as
to permit the government to set the price of natural gas at the
well-head (the Phillips Petroleum Case of 1954), thus discouraging the
search for new sources of natural gas and meanwhile encouraging
consumers to be wasteful of gas because of the government-set low price.
Indeed, it has enabled the government to create an energy shortage where
in nature no energy shortage exists. 6 These and thousands of
other intrusions into the free market have been brought about by these
court decisions, giving to the federal government tremendous regulatory
powers never granted in the Constitution of this republic. 7
And yet, in numerous polls throughout the last decade,
a majority of Americans appear to believe that what is needed are more
controls, not fewer. The majority have no idea of the cost of these
controls: the tremendously expensive and wasteful regulatory apparatus,
the ball and chain it places on production, the countless men and women
who would have helped to create a prosperous economy, who would (for
example) have found natural gas and sold it at market price (and with
greater abundance, the price would have come down). The majority see
only that "we think the price is too high," and vote to control the
producers. And thus they kill the goose that lays the golden egg. The
minority who see clearly enough what is happening are outvoted at the
polls. Such is the course of democracy.
The General Welfare
The federal government has also assumed enormous powers
through a distortion of the phrase "the general welfare." In the first
Congress, in 1789, a bill was introduced to pay a bounty to fishermen at
Cape Cod, as well as a subsidy to certain farmers. James Madison said:
"If Congress can employ money indefinitely to the general welfare, they
may take the care of religion into their own hands; they may appoint
teachers in every state, county, and parish, and pay them out of the
public treasury: they may take into their own hands the education of
children, establishing in like manner schools throughout the Union: they
may seek the provision of the poor ... [all of which] would subvert the
very foundations, and transmute the very nature of the limited
government established by the people of America."
And so Congress rejected the bill, and Thomas Jefferson
said with relief, "This will settle forever the meaning of the phrase
'general welfare,' which, by a mere grammatical quibble, has
countenanced the general government in a claim of universal power." It
is an irony of history that the Hydra that Jefferson thought he had laid
to rest has within our own century grown a hundred new heads, each of
them aimed at our liberty.
The Constitution read: "Congress shall have the power
to lay and collect taxes, duties, imports and excises, to pay the debts
and provide for the defense and general welfare of the United States."
This meant that the national government could raise money only and spend
money only to carry out its enumerated powers. They thought it
ridiculous to construe two words "general welfare" as if they superseded
the detailed enumeration of specific powers, rather than as merely
summarizing them. The two words were always interpreted in the latter
way by the Supreme Court during the first century and a half of American
history. Their meaning, they held, could be changed only by amendment to
the Constitution.
Yet today the amount of transfer payments-to promote
"the general welfare"-takes up almost half the budget; more than that,
if one includes all the entitlement programs. Moreover, the majority of
Americans apparently consider all these things as their right. Those
receiving money from the federal government now outnumber those who
labor to sustain it. The resulting level of taxation, as well as
national indebtedness, is causing the republic to hemorrhage to death in
the name of the democracy.
Market Alternatives
Without the vast bureaucracy created through the
regulatory agencies, free-market alternatives could be devised. For
example, "Building codes and fire codes could presumably be replaced
quite easily by privately enforced codes drafted by insurance companies.
Few developers would construct hazardous firetraps if they knew
beforehand that they could not acquire insurance for their buildings.
And as Bernard Siegan brilliantly demonstrated in his 'Non-zoning in
Houston,' 8egregious, incompatible property uses will not
often cohabit if land use regulations were summarily abolished.
Restrictive covenants that run with the land, renewable at intervals of
several decades, could very expeditiously insure that a slaughterhouse
will not locate in the middle of Shaker Heights, Beverly Hills, or Boca
Raton. If one were so unfortunate as to find one's house suddenly within
proximity of a noisome chemical plant a remedy would lie in nuisance
law, for no one has a right to use his property in such a way as to
adversely affect another's enjoyment of his property." 9
Democracy vs. the Market
The only thing that can increase a nation's standard of
living is greater production. And anything that inhibits that production
makes the nation poorer. If a farmer or manufacturer has part of his
output taken away from him for distribution to others, he will be less
motivated to produce in the future, If he is regulated by men from the
Department of Agriculture who trample over his fields to determine how
much corn he has planted, if the factory owner is regularly fined for
trivial offenses that shouldn't be offenses at all (but are only
contrary to rules set up by the government regulatory agency), he will
sooner or later be forced into bankruptcy or to continue production
under great difficulties (and higher prices). And if the government pays
the farmer money to grow or not to grow crops, this increases the burden
of every taxpayer in the land without any increase of production.
In a democracy, all such processes are easily
sanctioned by popular outcries: "He's a profiteer - take it away from
him." "He's getting too much-give it to us." People who haven't
succeeded, or weren't willing to make the sacrifices he made, will do
all they can to take it away from him after he has succeeded. A
democracy easily becomes dominated by the morality of envy. A fickle
mob, unaware of the facts of basic economics, but easily swayed by
demagogues demanding as their right the fruits of the labor of others,
can easily bring about the passage of laws which will inhibit
production, destroy the free market, and in the end lead to such
shortages and bottlenecks in production that they result, just as Plato
said, in riots, calls for "law and order," and dictatorship.
Only a republic, in which the powers of the government
are constitutionally limited, can avoid this fate. That is why the
Founding Fathers were careful to create this nation as a republic, so
that each person could determine his own destiny and not have it
determined by others, whether by the tyranny of one (dictatorship) or of
a few (oligarchy), or of many (democracy). "It is the blessing of a free
people, not that they live under democratic government, but that they do
not." 10 If the return to a republic is not achieved, Alexis
de Tocqueville's prediction of a century and a half ago may yet come
true: that the American government will become for its citizens "an
immense and tutelary power, which takes upon itself alone to secure
their gratifications, and to watch over their fate.... For their
happiness such a government willingly labors, but it chooses to be the
sole agent and the only arbiter of that happiness: it provides for their
security, foresees and supplies their necessities, facilitates their
pleasures, manages their principal concerns, directs their industry,
regulates the descent of property, and subdivides their inheritances -
what remains, but to spare them all the care of thinking and all the
trouble of living? ... The will of man is not shattered, but softened,
bent, and guided; men are seldom forced by it to act, but they are
constantly restrained from acting; such a power does not destroy, but it
prevents existence; it does not tyrannize, but it compresses, enervates,
extinguishes, and stupefies a people, till each nation is reduced to
nothing better than a flock of timid and industrious animals, of which
the government is the shepherd." 11
Indeed, it is not difficult to make a case for the view
that what Tocqueville predicted has already come to pass.
Perpetual Childhood
ABOVE this race of men stands an immense and
tutelary power, which takes upon itself alone to secure their
gratifications, and to watch over their fate. That power is absolute,
minute, regular, provident, and mild. It would be like the authority of
a parent, if, like that authority, its object was to prepare men for
manhood; but it seeks on the contrary to keep them in perpetual
childhood: it is well content that the people should rejoice, provided
they think of nothing but rejoicing. For their happiness such a
government willingly labours, but it chooses to be the sole agent and
the only arbiter of that happiness: it provides for their security,
foresees and supplies their necessities, facilitates their pleasures,
manages their principal concerns, directs their industry, regulates the
descent of property, and subdivides their inheritances-what remains, but
to spare them all the care of thinking and all the trouble of living?
Thus it every day renders the exercise of the free
agency of man less useful and less frequent; it circumscribes the will
within a narrower range, and gradually robs a man of all the uses of
himself.
Alexis De Tocqueville, Democracy in America
At the time of the original publication, John Hospers
was a professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of
Southern California, Los Angeles. He was the first Libertarian Party
candidate for the presidency of the United States (1972). He was the
editor of the philosophical magazine, The Monist. His books in June
1984 were Understanding the Arts (Prentice-Hall) and Human Conduct
(2nd ed. Harcourt Brace).
1 See S. I. Benn and Richard Peters, Social Principles
and the Democratic State (London: Allen & Unwin, 1959), Chapter 15.
Also published as a Collier-Macmillan paperback entitled Principles of
Political Thought.
2 Plato, The Republic, translation by Francis M.
Cornford (London: Oxford University Press, 1941), pp. 195-6.
3 Rose Wilder Lane, The Discovery of Freedom (New York:
Arno Press, 1943), pp. 207-8.
4 Rose Wilder Lane, op. cit., p. 203.
5 Newton Garber, Of Men and Not of Law (Greenwich,
Conn.: Devin-Adair, 1962), pp. 13 ff. See also Philip Kurland, ed., The
Supreme Court and the Constitution (University of Chicago Press, 1960),
and the recent book by Henry M. Holzer, Sweet Land of Liberty? (Costa
Mesa, Calif.: Common Sense Press, 1983), for many other examples.
6 0n the so-called energy crisis, see for example C. V
Myers, Money and Energy (Darien, Conn.: Soundview Books, 1980), and
Lindsey Williams, The Energy Non-Crisis (Wheatridge, Colo.: Worth
Publishing Co., 1980).
7 Dan Smoot, The Business End of Government (Belmont,
Mass.: Western Islands, 1973), p. 83. See also Alan Stang, The 0shacrats
(from the same publisher).
8 Bernard Siegan, "Non-Zoning in Houston," Journal of
Law and Economics, Vol. 13 (1970); and Land Use without Zoning
(Lexington Books, 1972, Chapter 2).
9 Ellen Frankel Paul, "On Three 'Inherent Powers of
Government,' " The Monist, Vol. 66 No. 4 (Oct. 1983), pp. 539-40.
10 Richard Taylor, "The Basis of Political Authority,"
the Monist, Vol. 66 No. 4 (Oct. 1983), p. 471. See also Richard Taylor,
Freedom, Anarchy, and the Law (Prentice-Hal 1, 1973).
11 Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, pp.
579-80 of the edition edited by Henry Steele Commager, 1946.
Reprinted with permission from The
Freeman, a publication of The Foundation for Economic Education, Inc.,
June 1984, Vol. 34, No. 6.