Libertarianism Versus Conservatism:
|
By Chris R. Tame and Gerry Frost |
1 | Gerry Frost: What Good Is The State? |
---|---|
II | Chris R. Tame: The Bankruptcy of Conservatism |
III | Gerry Frost: Libertarians Versus Liberty |
IV | Chris R. Tame: Libertarianism Versus Conservatism |
V | Chris R. Tame: Some Second Thoughts |
ISSN 0953 7783 * ISBN 1 870614 67 4 A publication of the Libertarian Alliance © 1989: Libertarian Alliance; Chris R. Tame; Gerry Frost. This debate first appeared in Free Life, Vol. 3, No. 1 (1982) and Vol. 3, No. 2 (1983). Chris R. Tame is the founder and Secretary of the Libertarian Alliance. He edited A Bibliography of Freedom for the Centre For Policy Studies and has contributed to such journals as The Jewish Journal of Sociology, Science and Public Policy, and Economic Affairs amongst many others, and has delivered papers to academic conferences and universities in Britain, the USA and Poland. Gerry Frost has been a leader-writer for The Evening Standard as well as former Secretary and Director of the Centre For Policy Studies. He is currently Director of the Institute for European Defence and Strategic Studies. He contributes regularly to such journals as Encounter and Survey and is co-author of Protest and Perish: A Critique of Unilateralism. He spoke on "The Soviet Threat" at the LA Conference Which Way Western Foreign Policy? The views expressed in this publication are those of the author, and not necessarily those of the Libertarian Alliance, its Committee, Advisory Council or subscribers. |
![]() 25 Chapter Chambers, Esterbrooke Street, London SW1P 4NN.
|
A Conservative View Gerry Frost
Libertarians and liberals show little understanding of the nation and little understanding and less enthusiasm for the state.
Friedrich Hayek does perceive a major role for the state. But many liberals tend to allow it only a minimal or nightwatchman role. They look upon it as some naughty child who doesn't know its place and constantly needs to be reminded of it. Or they grudgingly admit its necessity in certain limited respects but regard it with the same degree of enthusiasm with which Mrs. Thatcher might open a Christmas card from Peter Walker. The view that the state represents an invariable threat to freedom seems to me to be wrong, to represent a shallow, one-dimensional, almost monomaniacal view of politics. A strong state is a necessary precondition of individual liberty. A strong and effective state and liberty are mutually sustaining. Wherever you find people enjoying freedom it is within the context of the state. Individual liberty, along with order and justice, is one of the achievements of civilised modern states. To what other source can we look for protection or redress in the event of our freedom being threatened by others? The state may not do that job very well now and perhaps it does not do it because it has taken too much upon itself, but that is not to justify the conclusion that the state should be somehow got rid of or eroded until the point where it scarcely exists. Supposing it was somehow dissolved in the way that anarcho-capitalists like Murray Rothbard or libertarians like the ghastly Ayn Rand favour, what would prevent the most powerful, charismatic among us from leading a faction that would tyrannise or exploit the rest? Who would prevent rival factions from settling their disputes violently, like feudal barons or rival protection gangs? There would be no independent and impartial authority to adjudicate between them, the recognised and legitimate authority having been abolished.
The point I am making is that when an individual finds himself out of his or her social context, the customary restraints, the institutionalised curbs and inhibitions no longer exist to reign in appetites and impulses and some run riot.
The consequence of man's intellectual limitations require that he avail himself of the bank and capital of ages when deciding political and social issues, rather than relying on his own strictly limited stocks of reason. Man is a social creature and the state is a natural extension of man's social character.
Ordinary people have little difficulty in grasping all this, perhaps because they rely on tradition and custom to regulate their attitudes towards the state. Indeed, many ordinary people have shown themselves ready to die for particular nation states. On the whole they do not appear to resent the claims made upon them in times of war or national emergency. Many of those who fought in the last war said they were fighting for freedom. The self-same people said on other occasions that they were fighting for their country. They saw no contradiction between the two; they realised that liberty depends on the preservation of a traditional social framework.
Every conceivable social ill is attributed to a lack of freedom; little account is taken of circumstance or particular conditions. The universal panacea therefore is more freedom, and the unthinking corollary of this is often less state. This may well be a cure to particular problems. But it is not the universal panacea that Libertarians suppose it to be. An extension of individual liberty will not solve problems in Northern Ireland or Brixton.
Freedom (or more freedom) in the abstract, idealised way beloved by the modern liberal, all round! Freedom for the Saudis, the Pygmies, the Zulus! The Shah of Persia extended individual liberties in his country and was always being pressed by liberals to go further. The result of that and of rapidly rising income was the collapse of traditional bonds which held that country together. Are we still confident that more liberty would be an unmixed blessing for the Iranians? Would either the Saudis or the oil consuming nations of the West benefit if we pressed the Saudi leaders to grant their peoples a much greater degree of liberty? This seems highly questionable. Unlike libertarians, conservatives believe that liberty flourishes in a particular kind of context. They tend to work for elimination of concerted evils rather than the realization of abstract goals. Conservatives, who know that politics is about the correct application of power according to circumstances, deal with the here and now.
Just in case you think that these lessons have no point in socialist or socially fragmented Britain, consider the way in which libertarian ideologues speak and behave. They dismiss their critics as fools or cretins or crooks. They describe people as "sound" or "unsound". They employ the vocabulary of Right-wing Stalinists. They attribute foul motives. Read their tracts and pamphlets -- many are full of the most extreme vituperation. How will such utterances contribute to the enlargement of freedom? I suggest that it will lead to a heightening of political squabbles and tensions and result in greater intolerance, which in the end will lead to the denial of liberty.
Those liberals who believe in some kind of state, albeit of extremely modest proportions, can normally tell you exactly what the state should or should not do, that is to say they set out its function in fine Utopian style. But Popper, the great man who popularized the phrase "Re Open Society" and indeed, Hayek, specifically warn against social blueprints of that kind and they warn of the very great dangers entailed in attempting to apply such blueprints.
The state is not the invariable enemy of liberty and the legitimate exercise of state authority is in my view the necessary concomitant of liberty not its opponent. Burke wrote of the Utopians of his own age: "In the groves of their academy, at the end of every vista you see nothing but the gallows." It may seem paradoxical to you to say that in their opposition to the state the libertarians and the extreme liberals present a glimmering of the same danger. But that is what I believe.
Madame Roland's famous words on the way to the guillotine, "Oh liberty, what crimes are committed in thy name!" should perhaps be re-phrased: "what misconceptions are presented in thy name!"
Libertarians are as concerned with social order, with the defence of life and property as anyone. What makes them distinctive is that they propose Libertarian solutions to the problems which led Hobbes, Burke and their followers to advocate the strong centralised authority of the state.
Anarcho-capitalists think that the best way of achieving "law and order" is by removing the monopoly of a single coercive agency from the provision of restitutive, protective and adjudication services, and putting those services into the hands of competing, commercial organisations.
The reasoning behind this belief is not particularly new; it has been applied to other important areas of human life for the past two hundred years. It is simply a logical extension of pluralism -- the idea that the best way to safeguard the individual's security is to divide power, to deny it a monopoly so that a many-headed hydra has to work that much harder, and be that much more determined, if it desires to take over society.
No anarcho-capitalists are naive enough to believe that the power-hungry will disappear in a stateless society. What will happen is that they will be denied the monopoly institutions, the automatic routes to power, which provide them with the instruments of coercion even in democratic societies.
The existence of just two competing security agencies, receptive to consumer demand, can do far less harm to the individual and be far more motivated to defend his/her interests than monopoly agencies in even multi-party systems. For a change of parties in democracies usually signifies no more than a change of "management policies" for the police, the forces and the judiciary; the structure of the provision of these services remains the same: they may reflect the imbalance of a disarmed society "protected" by an armed monopoly.
Despite Frost's attempt to portray Libertarians as starry-eyed dreamers he, like all advocates of non-market, "political" institutions, subscribes to the hopelessly optimistic belief that agents of the state will achieve a personality transformation so that they will be more able to exercise civilised and ethical judgement than private organisations and individuals. This assumption, usually hidden, but made explicit in, for example, the work of Hannah Arendt, is the basis of most modern forms of statism.
Libertarians take a more realistic, hard-headed view, often inspired by their reading of Von Mises and other economists of both the Austrian and Chicago Schools. We believe there is no magic formula that will make state adjudication more "independent and impartial" than that performed by private individuals. If all power corrupts, as Lord Acton observed, then coercive monopoly power is a dangerous thing indeed.
The entire law merchant backed by a court system was founded and developed by those individuals who had an interest in its development quite independent of the state. The same applies to admiralty law which deals with seafaring, shipping and salvage.
T. Anderson and P. J. Hill in their essay, "An American Experiment in Anarcho-Capitalism: The Not so Wild, Wild West" (Journal of Libertarian Studies, Vol. III, No. 1, 1979) have argued that the so-called "Wild West" was not, in fact, without a system of law and order before the state stepped in, and that a crime wave only occurred after the state replaced the private agencies.
Anthropologists and other scholars have provided evidence of how ancient societies had highly developed non-state legal systems. Iceland and ancient Ireland are particularly good examples, the latter dealt with by Joseph Peden in "Stateless Societies: Ancient Ireland" (Libertarian Forum, April 1971) and "Property Rights in Celtic Irish Law" (Journal of Libertarian Studies, Vol. 1, No. 2, 1977). Other notable works are Tribes Without Rulers, edited by J. Middleton and D. Tait (Routledge, London, 1968); "Stateless Society" by A. Southall in the International Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences, Vol. 15 (Macmillan, London, 1968); and Society Against the State by P. Clastres (Blackwell, Oxford, 1977).
Far from being a bastion of order and security, the state has proved to be not only society's greatest thief, its biggest threat to security and to peace, but also usually a poor counter-force to violence and theft by others. Not least of the reasons for this is the fact that monopoly state agencies can afford to be less responsive to demands for adequate protection and penalties that actually work, for exactly the same reason that British Telecom provides such a shoddy, inefficient service.
One important consequence of taking protection, law and adjudication out of the market is that these services cease to be consumer oriented. They cease to be concerned with the victim, a feature of modern "justice"e; which is becoming increasingly apparent. The principle of restitution, in which the offender as far as possible paid back the victim, was enshrined in English common law, which evolved independently of central authority (see Bruno Leoni, Freedom and the Law, Nash, Los Angeles, 1972).
There are in anarcho-capitalist societies structural checks, balances and brakes on the acquisition of coercive power that would be far more efficient than those in liberal democratic regimes. These are discussed in detail in Murray Rothbard's For a New Liberty (Collier-Macmillan, New York, 1973); David Friedman's The Machinery of Freedom (Harper and Row, New York, 1974); and J. Wollstein and M. and L. Tannehill's Society Without Government (Arno Press, New York, 1972).
Any commercial, consumer-oriented organisation making a bid for coercive monopoly power would lose far more than just a battle if the attempt failed (as it is likely to do in a heavily armed society prone to litigation): a functioning business is dependent for survival on its reputation and goodwill.
The role of private arbitration would be even more important in an anarcho-capitalist society than it is in our own, where it already resolves a great many business disputes via social and economic sanctions and the bonding system.
If custom is to function at all it must be spontaneous, that is, freely held. Given the way that Frost uses tradition as an argument for statism, it is ironic that about two hundred years ago conservatives were defending spontaneous "folkways" against liberal-rationalist legislation! One of the greatest twentieth century Libertarians, Albert Jay Nock, was an ardent defender of particular traditions, and of the role of tradition in history. In his great work, Our Enemy, The State (Free Life Editions, New York, 1973) Nock stresses the conflict between what he terms "social power" and "state power", the former the nexus of customs, trends and institutions evolved by the people to serve them, the latter the brute force of the state, the tool of particular groups and individuals to impose their values and goals upon society. Frank Chodorov explored similar themes in The Rise and Fall of Society (Devin-Adair, New York, 1959).
Unlike other social theorists, Libertarians do not have a moral blueprint ready for their ideal society (except, of course, for the non-aggression principle): such a blueprint would be incompatible with the spirit of Libertarian pluralism. It seems likely that most people will retain a blend of cautious conservatism and adaptability to change, while more avant garde minorities will have complete freedom to follow their lifestyles, as long as they are non-coercive, on their own property and in their own communities. That state and custom do not have to go together is evidenced by the many stateless societies of primitive tribes which were nevertheless rigidly bound by traditional rules of behaviour.
Frost supports the claim that the state is a "natural extension of man's social character". Quite the reverse is true: it is an extension of his anti-social character, because it attacks "social power", the many ways in which individuals and communities organise their activities.
What Libertarians seek is a framework of justice and liberty -- provided by the free market in the anarcho-capitalist version -- in which individuals and groups can pursue their distinctive traditions and mores in so far as they do not violently interfere with others. As Robert Nozick put it in Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Blackwell, Oxford, 1974): "Wittgenstein, Elizabeth Taylor, Bertrand Russell ... Picasso, Moses, Einstein, Hugh Heffner ... Frank Sinatra, Freud ... Ayn Rand ... Bobby Fischer, Emma Goldman ... you, and your parents. Is there really one kind of life which is best for each of these people?" (p. 310)
Frost's concept of a moral state enforcing morality or tradition can only cause conflict between different groups and individuals, all of whom battle for control of the state in order to defend themselves or attack others, to impose their "social context" or resist the imposition of others. Which contexts, which values, which traditions, Mr. Frost? Libertarians prefer the social context of liberty, a context which allows all sorts and conditions of people the space to pursue the good -- or the bad -- life as they see it. As Judy Tame said in an essay in Free Life: "freedom's special character is negative. It is a complete vacuum, a 'space' in which a variety of options, circumscribed only by 'the possible' are open. 'The possible' includes natural and human obstacles. Freedom is not the ability to do something in particular or be something in particular." ("Killing Freedom by Stealth", Spring, 1980.)
In his Omnipotent Government (Arlington House, New Rochelle, N.Y., 1969) written during the Second World War, Mises strove to analyse in detail the causes of the crises. His own words in the Introduction effectively refute Frost's -- and Roepke's -- claims: "It is the task of this present book to trace the outline of the changes and events which brought about the contemporary state of German and European affairs ... It deals both with history and with fundamental issues of sociology and economics. It tries not to neglect any point of view the elucidation of which is necessary for a full description of the world's Nazi problem ... Whoever wishes to understand the present state of political affairs must study history. He must know the forces which gave rise to our problems and conflicts." (pp. 8, 14)
Lack of freedom is the cause of countless problems, social disharmonies and suffering (for example, the explosion of organized crime as a result of the prohibition of alcohol in the USA; the increase of drug addiction as a result of anti-drug laws; the corruption of the Metropolitan Police as a result of laws against prostitution and other "vices"). Nevertheless, for Libertarians freedom remains the precondition, the necessary but not sufficient, basis for the pursuit of other values. The achievement of some of those goals I deem desirable -- the end of bigotry and superstition, the creation of the polite and orderly society, sexual enlightenment -- are quite clearly not achieved automatically by the creation of a free society. Such values are the product of persuasion, education, and agreement.
In Brixton government agencies have proved particularly inept at protecting the lives, liberty and property of citizens, black or white. While policemen waste their time bursting into private houses and coffee bars hunting for cannabis, old women remain prey to violence on the streets. The list of central and local government restrictions of freedom which have exacerbated Brixton's problems is endless: rent control; high rates; council housing; planning controls; victimless crimes such as smoking cannabis which help to alienate blacks from the police; non-market policing which can afford to be abusive to the black section of its "customers"; few alternatives to poor state education; and last but not least, a lack of political will on the part of those who make the decisions, to do what is necessary to give adequate protection from genuine crime to the ordinary people of Brixton.
It does not take a Libertarian to point out the error of Frost's third example as cases where individual liberty has not worked. Frost says that the Shah of Iran attempted to extend individual liberties, resulting in "the collapse of traditional bonds which held that country together."
The Shah followed a vigorous policy of technocratic, Keynesian statism, backed by the ferocity of the SAVAK secret police, estimated at between 30,000 and 60,000 strong. It has been well documented that under the Shah's regime tens of thousands of individuals were imprisoned, tortured and murdered.
Iran's modernization consisted of massive taxation, explosive inflation, centralized banking, an army of western and western trained Keynesian economists, macro-economic fine turning, price controls, Soviet-style "five year plans", centrally directed investment, prohibitions on private housing, and large state building schemes. This statism brought in its wake a network of graft and corruption, conferring unearned privileges and wealth on those with power and influence.
The reasons for the return of militantly traditional values in Iran are no doubt many and varied; what cannot be held responsible is individual liberty, for the simple reason that under the Shah vast areas of personal freedom did not exist. It is far more realistic to see the events in Iran as the product of a power struggle between westernised, secular statists and the religious authorities, a tension which is common in developing countries.
Roy Childs made an important contribution to analysis of the Iranian revolution in his essay, "The Iranian Drama" (Libertarian Review, February, 1980). Here Childs points out that when the Shah tried to promote genuinely modern values (for example, the liberation of women) he did so gun in hand. This, predictably, created the bigoted, reactionary backlash that occurred.
Far from providing an argument for statism, Iran underlines my earlier argument against the conservative idea that the state can be used to enforce morality, social behaviour and mores. In Roy Childs' words: "This indeed is the continuing contradiction which lies behind so much of the 'modernization' or 'Westernization' which is taking place in the Third World ... there are in fact always two routes to progress: the path of free, spontaneous development, of free men and women engaging in voluntary exchanges, producing economic growth through their own voluntary savings and investment, changing their own social mores through their own growing understanding; and the path of state coercion, violence and planning, which imposes a preconceived notion of progress on men and women at the point of a gun. The Pahlavi dynasty has always followed the second route, backed by Western governments anxious to use Iran's oil resources for their own benefit." (p. 32)
Equally untrue is Frost's claim that Libertarians are concerned only with abstract, idealized freedom, and not with anyone's freedom in particular. A passing acquaintance with Libertarian literature would disabuse anyone of such a fallacy. From Spencer's Social Statics to Mises's Liberalism, from Rand's Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal to Hosper's Libertarianism, from Rothbard's For A New Liberty to Machan's Human Rights and Human Liberties, Libertarian works are replete with analyses of specific freedoms or our lack of them. The diverse American Libertarian press -- Reason, Libertarian Review, Libertarian Forum, Liberty, Free Texas, New Libertarian, Objectivist Forum, The Freeman etc. -- presents an ongoing spectacle of Libertarian analysis to countless specific issues such as the railways, education, private health insurance, urban renewal schemes in New York, and so on.
In contrast, consider conservatism. Here we find little more than a rag-bag of phrases about liberty and tradition, with very little specificity and analysis. At their best, conservatives like Frost appear to want to pick and choose in a supermarket of values, taking a little liberty here, a little authority there. The logic of their choice seems arbitrary, based on the easy principle: freedom for anything I like or am indifferent about; no freedom for anything I dislike.
When it comes to abstraction, Frost's typically conservative consignment of the non-Western world to backwardness and statism on the grounds that it is not ready for liberty (or does he think they can never be free?) is a spectacular example. I wonder if Frost has ever taken the trouble to consider what this inhumane principle actually means in concrete terms for the people of the poorer countries? The prolongation of poverty and despair, of hunger and disease, of torture and other violence, of endless toil under landed and industrial magnates and political masters, the condemnation of independent-minded women to purdah and ceaseless child-bearing ... this is what Frost's abstract traditionalism means in practice.
Frost apparently shares Enoch Powell's unabashed relativism which in effect takes the attitude "I'm all right, Jack" with respect to ourselves in the West, and condemns the rest of humanity to poverty and suffering because they were not lucky enough to be born within the pale of Britain's traditional liberties. In other words, the "good life" is for those of European descent only, because they thought of it first. In this way, conservatives like Powell and Frost raise historical accident to an inhumanely abstract principle. What could be more cut off from concrete reality than the consignment of millions of individuals to backwardness and despair in the name of an assertion -- relativism -- found in sociological textbooks?
Since Frost does not give specific examples I find is somewhat difficult to deal with his claim. From my very wide reading of Libertarian literature I have noticed that the tone is usually serious, courteous and scholarly. It is a mistake frequently made to confuse vigorous argument with abuse.
Individuals vary in their tastes and temper, and in their propensity to refer to spades, bloody shovels or agricultural implements. It is probably true that Libertarians use stronger language than conservatives, but we do not think that conservative moderation is something to emulate! If Frost had observed Libertarians at work and play more closely he might have noticed that friends and colleagues can engage in vigorous debate with one another without ceasing to be friendly afterwards.
Frost himself is certainly not immune from the use of vituperative and immoderate language when referring to Libertarians; we have, he says, a "mystical glaze" in our eyes, Ayn Rand is "ghastly" (no reason given), reasoned argument is traduced as "furious protestations" and our "utopian" visions will lead to "nothing but the gallows". Even conservatives find it appropriate to employ abuse at times; what a pity it should be directed at exponents of liberty rather than liberty's enemies.
The remedy is the removal of the state from its role as patron and benefactor of the unions, not more legislation creating further inequalities under the law between citizens. As a Libertarian Alliance leaflet says, "Trade Unions should be voluntary associations (like chess clubs, charities, churches or business corporations), free to run their internal affairs as they please ... [they] ought to be treated by the law just like any other voluntary association, without privileges or special disabilities."
Frost claims that we need an "authoritative state", a state which "commands respect, allegiance and affection" in order to deal with the unions and other problems. In his view this is incompatible with the minimal, night-watchman state and with liberalism. It is difficult to see why a state, limited in the areas in which it is allowed to intervene, should not nevertheless be vigorous, authoritative and respected in its own domain. Anarcho-capitalists, of course, accept no function for the state at all, but they still recognise the importance for an anarcho-capitalist society of respect and affection for its institutions (if you like, a nationless "patriotism"). No society can persist for long, not least a Libertarian one, without a positive commitment on the part of its members to its way of life and to its system of authority and justice. This is a concept -- "legitimacy" which can be found in any political science and sociology textbook, and is not an insight peculiar to conservatives.
Gerry Frost's essay suggests that conservatism is ideologically bankrupt, and that it has no claim to the interest of those seeking individual liberty.
Chris Tame's reply ("The Bankruptcy of Conservatism") to my article "What Good is the State" sadly demonstrated that I failed dismally in the task I had set myself. This was to show to friends of libertarian persuasion, in a gentle if provocative way, they they perhaps do not after all possess the whole of political truth, if such there is; that temperance (not to be confused with "moderation" in its modern political sense), intellectual humility, and scepticism are essential to the well-being of a pluralist society; that those who seek liberty do not do their cause much good by treating with contempt those with whom they disagree; that there are unperceived dangers lurking in the universalism and utopianism of much libertarian writing; that adherence to libertarian, liberal or conservative views should imply a mode of discourse as well as particular views, and that self-deprecation is often a sign of judgement and is therefore to be cherished; and, most importantly, that adherence to the single, dominant cause and the theme of unlimited freedom will -- paradoxically -- help strengthen the fetters that bind us.
However, writing with all the certainty of one who has recently had the truth exposed to him by Divine Revelation, displaying the intellectual humility that one associates with Alfred Sherman and the degree of self-deprecation of Edward Heath, Chris Tame concludes triumphantly: "Gerry Frost's essay suggests that conservatism is ideologically bankrupt, and that it has no claim to the interest of those seeking individual liberty."
What follows is dedicated to all those ideological bankrupts who, on Tame's definition, appear to make up the entire population save the membership of the Libertarian Alliance.
While I prefer liberal ideologies to Marxist ones, this exclusivity, this sense of being virtuous in a sea of vice, does strike me as disagreeable. Why is it that those who should presumably adopt a live and let live attitude towards life do in fact approach it with the intensity of a Calvinist suffering from constipation and so often display the temperament and language of authoritarians?
However, I leave this question to psychology students in search of a PhD thesis, in order to make the following points about Chris Tame's critique.
Tame misunderstands me (and, more importantly, Burke) when he says that I reject reason. Traditional conservatives simply assert that reason is fallible and that there are mysteries which the human intellect cannot immediately penetrate. Hence the need to take notice of "the capital and bank of ages".
I do not assert that past attempts to understand the world are always superior to one's own and I did not say that they were. I merely assert that in an age in which there is a pathetic and unworthy worship of everything that is new and trendy we ought to better understand and value that which has been tried and tested and which has worked over the years (e.g., markets, parish councils, Oxford and Cambridge, the WRVS, the laws of supply and demand). I believe that many disasters, e.g, reorganisation of local government, "fine tuning" etc. would have been avoided had so many intellectuals not concluded that all ancient institutions were "Past it" and that everything written before the last decade was passé unless it happened to be by Marx or Engels.
Chris Tame implies that conservatives have no means of selecting between different ideas and principles formulated in the past. This is not of course the case. Tories are empirical, pragmatic, sceptical, tolerant, and have a particular view of man and humanity. They can and should judge on the basis of this distinctive philosophical outlook.
Chris Tame also asserts that accumulated wisdom is due to past acts of individual rationality. Not so, Mr. Tame: custom, tradition, prejudice, instinct, imagination, and luck, have all played their part. His description of the process by which we acquire learning also overlooks the extent to which we are constantly comparing the ideas and experience of the present with the established truths and experience of the past.
What I was endeavouring to say was that the dilemmas of human society are complex and various. It is extremely arrogant to suppose that the application of a single panacea -- whether more freedom or some other social good -- would help alleviate the hardships of various people in various situations in different parts of the world of which we are all more or less ignorant. It might very well have the opposite effect. It is difficult to understand what is happening in one's own country: still harder to fathom the mysteries and complexities of peoples whose perceptions and attitudes are remotely different. Chris Tame suggests the whole matter can be cleared up if I read a noted Libertarian expert on Iran: I wonder whether it is the author's libertarianism or his deep knowledge of Iranian ways that commends itself to Mr. Tame.
As for his suggestion that I am inhumane because I aver that there are differences in the mores and attitudes of different races, it sounds like the authentic voice of the Loony Left. I shall assume that Chris has employed Ken Livingstone on one of those numerous MSC grants to assist him in drafting the article. I refuse to take the point seriously because if I did I would have to treat it with contempt.
Finally, I plead guilty to the charge of being ideologically bankrupt, but since conservatives have always eschewed ideology as such, it is no great admission. Indeed, to make the charge is rather like condemning a teetoller for failing to stand his round. However, there is, I believe, a distinctive conservative way of looking at the world: it is not based on the single, over-riding cause of unlimited liberty because conservatives believe that if you seek unlimited freedom or unlimited anything else, you will end up with unlimited despotism: but I am inclined to the view that it better serves the cause of individual liberty than the strident simplicities of libertarianism.
I fear that Gerry Frost's rebuttal of my critique of conservatism only serves to underline not merely the ideological, but intellectual, bankruptcy of conservatism.
Now it is, alas, true that libertarianism has not proved immune from secular religiosity, and from the whole range of pathological motivations that have manifested themselves in every other ideology or intellectual system, from socialism to conservatism, from Christianity to Freudianism. I will leave it to readers to decide, however, whether my writing gives evidence of such characteristics. Throughout our exchange, I should point out, it is Gerry Frost who has consistently employed the most extravagant abuse and name-calling, in place of reasoned argument.
Gerry Frost now argues that conservatives have a "distinctive philosophical outlook" enabling them to judge and select amongst traditions. Let us be told, then, the detailed, reasoned arguments for this outlook. Let us see its superiority to other outlooks demonstrated. Gerry, of course, does no such thing. He merely offers us a list of more or less appealing epithets -- "empirical", "pragmatic", "sceptical", "tolerant". The first three words are almost devoid of meaning. As for the last, one is left almost speechless by a conservative claiming tolerance as a major characteristic of his ideology. Conservatism and conservatives are constantly seeking the repression of ideas, values, life-styles, minorities and traditions they do not favour -- all in the name, of course, of social cohesion, or tradition, order, decency, the public good, etc.
Gerry Frost also attempts to rescue his position by shifting the meaning of words. He argues that "Chris Tame asserts that accumulated wisdom of the past is merely the product of past acts of individual rationality", whereas "custom, tradition, prejudice, instinct, imagination and luck, have all played their part." What he is doing here is dodging between "wisdom" meaning demonstrated truths, correct ideas, etc. and "wisdom" as useful or functional social patterns. Quite clearly, useful social functions have emerged from more than mere individual rationality. They have indeed emerged from "custom, tradition, prejudice, instinct, imagination and luck". No libertarian would deny this. In fact, libertarian scholars have spent much time analysing the "unintended consequences of human action", the economic interpretation of history, the complex ways in which social orders emerge -- for both good and evil -- from the interplay of many factors. But it is precisely the critical rational intelligence which performs this task of evaluation (not the credulous, uncritical tradition-bound mentality) and which judges precisely what is useful in a human context.
In fact, Gerry Frost is clearly right when he says that a society where "anything goes" is undesirable, perhaps even impossible. But no libertarian wants this. Libertarians want a society where life, liberty and property are maintained, where invasive coercion is prevented, and non-invasive actions are not interfered with. Clearly some sort of "broad consensus" is necessary, if by that we mean -- as libertarians mean -- adherence to non-aggressive behaviour. Many other values (politeness, rationality, benevolence etc., to name but a few) would also create a much more workable, enjoyable and productive society, and libertarians support such values.
Gerry Frost also misrepresents my arguments. He states that I suggested he was inhumane because he "aver(s) there are differences in the mores and attitudes of different races". I did no such thing. Clearly different ethnic, racial, national, linguistic and other groups do have different mores and attitudes. What I question is whether those different mores and attitudes are of equal moral status, and whether the present hegemony of particular values over particular groups should be sacrosanct and immune from criticism.
This debate was first published in 1982 and 1983. Looking back at it there is nothing very substantial I would want to add to my reply to Gerry Frost's critique of Libertarianism, although obviously all my points could be elaborated and made more persuasive. Gerry's arguments still seem to me to be wrongheaded and characterised by windy rhetoric and ill-tempered sarcasm and abuse.
Just as there are unsocial Socialists and unchristian Christians, so one can find coercive and immoral Libertarians. Indeed, as a result of some painful personal experience I would be disposed to concede the existence of quite a few individuals like this, individuals prepared to act in grossly coercive, dishonest and unpleasant ways and who use "libertarianism" as a mask or excuse (the old "for the good of the cause" ploy!) for their behaviour. This is explainable principally as being part of what I would want to describe as the "pathology of intellectuals". It is certainly not confined to libertarianism, but runs as a constant thread through all intellectual movements. It is something to do with the nature of intellectuals and intellectual movements per se, and is urgently in need of proper analysis. (Paul Johnson's widely criticised recent work Intellectuals is a welcome contribution, but much more is needed.) Insofar as Conservatism is much less intellectual it suffers to a lesser degree from the pathology of the intellectual. However, it does have its own distinctive failings, of which hypocrisy is the most striking. If I had a pound for each of the homophobic, Bible-bashing, purity-preaching Conservatives caught with their trousers down in homosexual relationships, adultery, affairs with underage girls, drug-taking, or pornography consumption I would be a wealthy man!
Back to the Pamphlets Index
Back to the Libertarian Alliance Home Page
The Libertarian Alliance
(LA@capital.demon.co.uk)